How we think about art is of continual interest to me. For example, why is there a tendency to make a distinction between fine art and craft? Is it that something possessing a practical utility makes it less than art? Or is it just a way to classify what kind of art it is? Or does it have something to do with our definition of art in the first place?
If an ancient Egyptian were to be transport through time and visited the Metropolitan Museum in NYC, he would find a section called Egyptian Art. He would recognize the objects but he might not understand the "art" designation. All the objects displayed had a utility associated with them. However, the concept of "art" as we know it didn't exist in the ancient world. Everything had a function, it could be beautiful but it had a practical purpose. Wendell Castle's furniture is utilitarian. However in my mind, it's art even though I can sit in it.
I came across an interesting article in the New York Times, written by Stephan Hayman, entitled "Giving Meaning to 'Art'. The first part of the article sheds light on the way our conceptual framework of thought affects how we relate to a tool vs. sculpture or utilitarian object vs. work of art. The second part deals with concepts of originality that are tangential to the subject of the post, but so fascinating I included it.
The
psychologist George E. Newman of the Yale School of Management studies how
people use “quasi-magical thinking” to intuitively determine the value of
certain objects. By analyzing celebrity auctions of John F. Kennedy or Marilyn
Monroe’s personal effects, he has shown that the price of a piece of
memorabilia is connected to how often it was thought to be used or touched by a
famous person — as if there’s a kind of real-world value placed on a celebrity’s
“essence.”
Recently,
Mr. Newman has switched his attention to the art world. In his latest paper,
published last month in the journal Topics in Cognitive Science and co-authored
by Daniel M. Bartels and Rosanna K. Smith, he staged a pair of experiments that
show how flimsy or essential the term “art” can be.
Mr.
Newman asked a group of Yale undergraduates to read a scenario about a plastic
object, which a college student had made with a wax mold. In half the
scenarios, the object was referred to as a tool; in the other half, it was
called a sculpture. The students were told that the object was destroyed in a
fire, but an exact duplicate of the original object was made using the same
mold. Then they were asked whether they believed the copy was essentially the
same object. Overwhelmingly, those who were told the object was a tool thought
the duplicate was the same object, while those who were told it was a sculpture
thought it wasn’t.
“Just
labeling something as ‘art’ really changed people’s intuitions,” Mr. Newman
said.
In a
second experiment, the researchers showed the students an image of an original
painting and said that, because of damage, a duplicate painting was
commissioned, identical in every way. The researchers then manipulated facts
about the original painting: that the artist had painted it himself and thought
it was among his very best works, or that he thought of it as “sell-out piece,”
got the idea for the design from another painter, and had an assistant execute
the painting.
The level
of “contagion” — the artist’s personal involvement with the original painting —
influenced opinions about the duplicate. In the cases where the artist did not
paint the work with his own hand or think highly of it, the participants
thought there wasn’t much difference between the copy and the original. In the
cases where the artist was personally invested in the original work, the copy
was seen as lesser than the other. “It is a copy,” one participant said. “It
has no soul.
“It’s
interesting that people have pretty detailed and sophisticated theories about
the things that are contributing to art’s value,” Mr. Newman said. “And
moreover that those ideas have not that much to do with what the artwork
actually looks like.”
No comments:
Post a Comment